Wednesday, October 2, 2019

Acceptance


Acceptance study 091919. PRB

Preface


I routinely write that fellow citizens may accept each 1) the U.S. Preamble’s proposition, 2) responsible human liberty and 3) human individual power, energy, and authority (HIPEA) to develop integrity. I plan to create a comprehensive list of acceptances. [Note: on 10/8/19, I discovered ACT, a mindfulness therapy. I plan to read a book or two---perhaps by Stephen Hayes then by Russ Harris to learn thoughts beyond or in parallel with my acceptance that you are human and acceptance of a public agreement to equity under statutory justice.] 

Further, I suggest that the standard for justice is fidelity to the-objective truth, [1] which is the ineluctable evidence by which truth is measured. Preparing this essay, I encountered this MW1 illustration of “literal”: “The story he told was basically true, even if it wasn't the literal truth.” This sentence implies the speaker’s evaluation and claim to know the literal truth. “The-objective-truth” expresses humility to the literal truth. I assert that I do not know much of the-objective-truth, and I rely on it.

In my eighth decade, I realize my quest, to be what I want to be, is a sequence of acceptances, beginning with acceptance that I am a human being. I chose to study the philosophy of “acceptance”. The study enhanced ongoing concern to encourage fellow citizens to voluntarily accept U.S. citizenship and to never invite fellow citizens to leave/emigrate. The U.S. Preamble (the preamble to the U.S. Constitution) offers individuals and collectives (societies) acceptance of responsible human liberty.

Dictionary information


Merriam-Webster (MW) online[2] has “acceptance, noun”:  the quality or state of being accepted or acceptable; the act of accepting something or someone; the fact of being accepted; acceptance of responsibility:  Law, an agreeing either expressly or by conduct to the act or offer of another so that a contract is concluded and the parties become legally bound; the act of accepting a time draft or bill of exchange for payment when due according to the specified terms; an accepted draft or bill of exchange.

The MW thesaurus divides words into two categories: 1) “a readiness or willingness to accept or adapt to a given circumstance” and 2) “permission given to do something.” The synonyms in both categories are abundant. Interesting to my purpose is the antonyms for Category 1: resistance, defiance, disobedience, intractability, recalcitrance, animosity, antipathy, enmity, hostility, ill will.

The category most interesting to my purpose is acceptance: “[the discipline] to accept . . . a given circumstance.”

Abstract


Much of philosophy of “acceptance” addresses intellectual constructs intended to avoid or resist actual reality. Reviewing 15 of perhaps thousands of philosophical articles which use the word “acceptance,” my criticisms follow, below.

Rules and codes are no substitute for the-objective-truth. Impartiality is an intention but not an option respecting the-objective-truth. On the other hand, in the absence of statutory justice (the worthy goal of perfection), an agreement to aid equity under law enforcement seems worthy. Some people think crime and other infidelities pay. Therefore, the public funds law enforcement. Research designed to prove a belief has no objectivity and may not yield discovery. Discovery usually affirms related theories and vice versa. Societies create rules that lessen individual encouragement to develop integrity to the-objective-truth. The individual may reserve some power, energy, and authority for the-objective-truth. Much like slavery, few would volunteer to be tolerated. In order to communicate, collaborate, and connect to discover the-objective-truth, the parties must establish mutual semantics; expressions are enhanced by words that suggest something, such as “humankind” rather than “man” when people past present and future is the subject. Acceptance without evidence is voluntary and may be honest yet lack integrity. Pursuing knowledge or probability as surrogates for the-objective-truth is unpromising or begs woe. The-objective-truth responds to neither reason, nor “conventional truths”, nor human awareness, nor intentions, nor assertion of the literal truth. Acceptance of the-objective-truth as standard for justice may asymptotically lead to the literal truth. Scientific research is the study of the-objective-truth, and it demands objectivity. Applying subjective statistics to study human psychology is a dubious practice. People who propose research without objectivity seem to value metaphysics. It is useful to be aware of proprietary abuses of “acceptance,” and awareness need not become a burden.

Study method


I searched the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy using “acceptance” and found 546 articles, considering the first twelve and skipping to a 13th choice. Within each article, I searched “acceptance” and copied the sections using the term. Then I read the information to extract my interpretation. Also, I found one article at the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy I felt essential. Their search method does not allow canvasing on one word, but search within a selected article indicates they might also have 546 articles containing “acceptance”.

The following is my analysis of each article I reviewed. I highlight acceptance to help the reader relate to the respective article’s usage. The articles are numbered to aid the summary that follows.

1.     Rule Consequentialism[3]

This article addresses acceptance of rules and codes more than accepting the-objective-truth. “Impartial” opinion seems recommended as the standard for morality. However, opinion is no substitute for the-objective-truth.

Impartiality seeks a margin from 100% to accommodate punishment of dissidents. The author claims, without evidence, that 90% “seems” defensible.

Impartiality seems sufficient to override personal objections, and everyone is expected to adopt “the rules whose universal acceptance will have the best consequences impartially considered” including efficiency among the society. “Such arguments suggest . . .  contractualism and rule-consequentialism,” the latter being questioned as potentially unacceptable respecting unintended consequences and also suitability for public acknowledgement.

The category “contractualism” might include the proposition that is offered to fellow citizens by the U.S. Preamble: communicate, collaborate, and connect for responsible human liberty.

2.     Constructive realism[4]

“Van Fraassen [claims]: Science aims to give us theories which are empirically adequate; and acceptance of a theory involves as belief only that it is empirically adequate.” Wikipedia tells us he argues for “skepticism toward the reality of unseen entities.”

Acceptability of a theory as the-objective-truth may result from its interconnected verification by other researched theories. Empirical research is the work to discover actual reality[5] whether actual reality is observed[6] or not; in other words, the research does not always succeed.

Acceptance involves discovery of factual existence as well as how to benefit from the facts. Benefits accrue not only from application to human endeavors but to order related research. Imagination is useful in assessing, proposing, selling, and gaining acceptance of new areas for research long before there is belief that the research will lead to discovery. Acceptance is not likely if benefits from the evidence cannot be established, so pure research is a difficult sell.

This practice cautions against metaphysics or speculation. Yet, pure research often wins acceptance without elements of belief, for example, on predicted benefits versus estimated research costs if the theory is proved.

If a researcher intends to prove a belief, there is no objectivity to order the work. The consequence of the work may be “observation” of falsehood. For example, someone who believes the earth is flat may “observe” that the sun revolves around the earth each day when in fact the earth rotates on its axis successively hiding then un-hiding the sun each 24 hours. “Thus, beliefs may express . . . perception when discovery is absent.”

I appreciate this affirmation of the role of discovery regarding the-objective-truth.

3.     Social institutions[7]

Human collectives create “social phenomena, including conventions, social norms and social institutions [establishing] institutional structure. Structure entails the specifications and public acceptance. For example, the U.S. Supreme Court has nine justices and its authority is accepted by the people. Some individuals do not hold the Supreme Court as a reliable authority.

Collective acceptance is the summation of individual actions and differs from the individual acceptances. The individuals communicate, collaborate, and connect without absolute consent or explicit contract.

4.     Toleration[8]

“The term ‘toleration’—from the Latin tolerare: to put up with, countenance or suffer—generally refers to the conditional acceptance of or non-interference with beliefs, actions or practices that one considers to be wrong but . . . should [neither] be prohibited or constrained [nor affirmed or accepted].”

“Conditional acceptance” seems an oxymoron. For example, there is no toleration for racism: “an unacceptable prejudice [cannot be] an ethical judgment.” This confusion comes about because there is no standard for tolerance. That is, tolerance is a subjective practice. In other words, tolerance is a matter of opinion. Perhaps “intolerance” is useful whereas “tolerance” only confuses communication, collaboration, and connection.

Writer Rainer Forst assigns four conceptions to explain connections involving tolerance:  permission (authority vs dissent), coexistence (conflict avoidance), respect (public conduct separated from private conduct), and esteem (responsible private behavior revered). In any of these connections, which party is anxious to accept the other’s tolerance?

Forst’s construction derives from the privation of standards for civic behavior. With public acceptance of the-objective-truth, a civic, civil, and legal standard is established without strife over religious beliefs. Individuals may observe manners, civility, and legality without compromising responsible religious beliefs.

In public, there is intolerance to any interjection of the mystery of whatever-God-is, a private pursuit.

5.     Mutual knowledge constraints on conversation[9]


In conversation, the listener often expresses acceptance of the speaker’s claims yet in privacy holds doubt. Therefore, experienced speakers carefully establish plausibility if not reliability in their word choices. The speaker takes the following precautions: uses expressions he knows to represent the experiences and observations that are common to the audience; has a purpose that is shared by the audience; cites reliable evidences for the claims; admits to perception, memory, and induction in forming opinion; avoids burdening the listener with confirmation of the evidences and builds on any prior acceptances they express; admits that not everyone in the audience has already had the experiences or observation to lend reliability to the claims; and is civic if not humble when a listener perceives they have reason not to accept the claims.

The speaker and listener share the burden that while expressions can intend to appeal to experiences and observations common to many individuals, universal commonality does not exist. Knowing this, listeners may clarify expressions before considering acceptance of the claims. During this clarification, the speaker may explore listener’s expressions so as to establish mutual comprehension. And they may exchange roles, listener becoming speaker. This iterative clarification may change the speaker’s words and phrases. If listener merely stonewalls speaker, communication, collaboration, and connection cannot occur.

Proprietary scholars have bemused the speaker-listener with the slogan “know your audience and use their terms.” This is often impossible even in person-to-person conversation. The consequence of placing the burden solely on the speaker is, for example, endless dialogue about God when no two people accept a common God. Consequently, I invite discussion about the mystery of whatever-God-is.

6.     The honesty of belief[10]


Everything derives from physics as E=mC2 or better expression of the origins of actual reality. Humans use imagination and reason to research physics’ unknowns. Researchers use discovery or ineluctable evidence to establish the-objective-truth in an asymptotic elimination of erroneous comprehension. Acceptance of imagination or reason without evidence is metaphysics---beyond objective experience or observation; otherworldly; infidelity. Some people honestly fall into metaphysics and thereby delay integrity.

Some proprietary scholars not only neglect actual reality but also deflate accepted reason by extoling faith, belief, hope, or fideism, bemusing integrity as subordinate to reason. Centuries ago, scholars labeled physics and its offspring “nature,” erroneously ruling reason to be superior. Some scholars still hold mathematics to be abstract or metaphysical. Some erroneously argue that if an idea has a strong construct, ineluctable evidence will eventually be discovered. Supposedly, acceptance of the construct may accelerate the discovery. For example, the benevolence of whatever-God-is may be proven someday.

“A warning is in order here: acceptance is typically a technical notion and characterizations of its nature and ethics differ radically in the literature. The ethicist of belief who wants to soften or supplement her view by appealing to some notion of permissible acceptance would need to say what acceptance is, how the two sorts of attitude differ, what sorts of norms govern each, and how they interact in a single subject.” Usually, acceptance without evidence is voluntary.

7.     A thirteenth century logic[11]


Acceptance of an expression is enhanced by words that suggest something. For example, “humankind” stands for people living in the past, present, and future. However, “man” indicates gender, may refer to the superior bipedal species, or in context may be unrelated to humankind; e.g., an object in a board game.

I appreciate this affirmation of my quest to create a glossary that is devoid of identity politics. For example, I claim that the U.S. Preamble proposes to fellow-citizens individual discipline rather than self-governance. Such discipline is suggested to all people.

8.     Conditional logic[12]


Scholarship in conditional logic considers actual reality, probability, and knowing. The purpose is semantics for “acceptance for conditionals, rather than a theory of truth.”

“[We] need a notion of acceptance capable of characterizing the acceptance of sentences that lack truth values but express important cognitive attitudes. . . focusing on . . . supposition and its corresponding conditional axioms.”

“ . . . [respecting] grammatical matters . . . this type of consensus supposition correlates [imperfectly] with the use of the indicative mood in English.”

In plain terms, the-objective-truth does not respond to scholarly schemes, such as “conditional logic”. This concept seems the most egregious offense against the-objective-truth among all the articles I reviewed.

9.     Skepticism 2300 years ago[13]


An ancient skeptic’s acceptance of “‘reasonable’ or tentative hypotheses [did] not require assenting to them.” In another scholarly analysis, “assent is a matter of reason or thinking, rather than the acceptance of a non-rational ‘impression’.”


Beyond impression, the-objective-truth does not respond to human reason.


10. Eighth century Buddhist thought[14]


Evaluating “competing Buddhist” philosophies: 1) “conventional truths . . . as being of the nature of consciousness,” and 2) “conventional acceptance of self-cognizing consciousness or reflexive awareness.” Either way, the purpose is salvation (perhaps especially as effected by Jesus Christ), and the method is individual consideration of philosophical priorities.

The-objective-truth responds to neither “conventional truths” nor human awareness.

11.  Collective intentionality[15]


“Collective intentionality is the power of minds to be jointly directed at objects, matters of fact, states of affairs, goals, or values and comes in a variety of modes, including shared intention, joint attention, shared belief, collective acceptance, and collective emotion.”

Collective acceptance is a central presupposition for the creation of a language, and of a whole world of symbols, institutions, and social status. Shared evaluative attitudes provide us with a conception of the common good. In virtue of this we can reason from the perspective of our groups, and conceive of ourselves in terms of our social identities and social roles. This again enables us to constitute group agents such as business enterprises, universities, or political parties.”

The only valid “common good” I know of is mutual, comprehensive safety and security, which is the proposition that is offered by the U.S. Preamble. The U.S. Preamble proposes freedom-from oppression so as to secure the individual liberty-to develop integrity. Some develop the liberty-to practice crime and are thus dissidents to freedom-from oppression. Due to the rule of law, dissidents invite woe.

“When an individual reasons or has attitudes in the ‘I-mode,’ she does function as a group member but her commitments relative to the respective attitudes are private, i.e., they regard her goals qua private person. When she reasons or has attitudes in the ‘we-mode,’ she functions as a group member and conceives of herself as being bound by and committed to what is collectively accepted and subject of collective commitment within the group.” Thus, collective acceptance becomes attitudes of collective commitment. Being a group member seems like voluntary subjugation excepting the special case of mutual, comprehensive safety and security.

“Such plural subjects, as a particular sort of social group, can be subjects of intentional states such as intentions, beliefs, and acceptance; this is the point at which the account regards the subject of collective intentionality.” For example, “the existence of money depends at least partly on collective intentional attitudes, or on a shared practice of treating certain pieces of paper, and not others, as money. [It] is not easy to see how an attitude, whether collective or not, can” achieve acceptance of a natural pragmatism.

This seems a case of over philosophizing. The exchange of labor for goods is not feasible in a bartering system. Money serves as the medium of exchange. A more interesting philosophical challenge is to compare money with bitcoin. Is bitcoin an instability of possible reward for commitment to risk? Can bitcoin be considered as a tool for the common good? Can money?

The-objective-truth does not respond to intentions.

12. The cost of cognitive standards[16]


When a people express “attitudes of acceptance of various norms or rules governing conduct and emotion” they invite circularity dictated by either the established norms or the intentions in constructing the norms. Resulting norms can be irrational and unjust.

“If this line of argument works it will allow non-cognitivism to gain the allegiance of those who wish to deny relativism while giving the motivations that lead to both it and non-cognitivism their due.” This dilemma is nullified when the standard is the-objective-truth.

13.  No emotions in the study of physics[17]


Accepting science as research and research’s object physics (expressed by Einstein’s general theory of relativity), I understand E=mC2 as the origin of everything including fiction. Fiction is speculation about what has not been discovered from ineluctable evidence. In other words, fiction is created from human imagination, the second incentive to enter the rigor of scientific research. Science is then the work to discover the origins of everything; everything evolved from physics.

Discovery requires integrity, and infidelity may be introduced into research during each the authorization, the design of experiments, the acceptance of experimental results, and promotion of conclusions.

Most research is authorized on cost versus risk; that is, cost versus the inverse of chance for research-success. Decisions are guided by prior discovery (understanding the-objective-truth) and the hypothesis’ compatibility with connecting theories. Emotions, neither of the research team, the press, nor the public should influence decisions. That is, experimental design is based-on and intended-to-increase discovery of the-objective-truth.

Philosophers challenge the principle that scientific research is objective. The fact that the decision to put a person on the moon can, through objective research, succeed, does not seem like ineluctable evidence to some philosophers. Others concede objectivity in physics research but deny that human psychology is physics even though the brain operates on electro-chemistry. Some assert that statistics can be applied to psychology as science, not admitting that researchers suspect statistics. On subjectivity and statistical studies, a dubious industry called “social sciences” hangs.

In the philosophical debate about scientific objectivity, the-objective-truth exists. In the pursuit of integrity about human psychology, subjective statistics is a dubious tool. I trust objectivity rather than “social science.”

14. Scientific unrealism[18]


As though the-objective-truth responds to opinion, this argument starts with the phrase “we are entitled to” as an arrogant disclaimer to “may”:  “Debates about scientific realism concern the extent to which we are entitled to hope or believe that science will tell us what the world is really like. Realists tend to be optimistic; antirealists do not.”

Scientific researchers trust that they are collaborating on interconnected theories. Newton’s gravity suffered doubt “with the increasing acceptance of Maxwell’s theory of electromagnetism” then was affirmed as a special case of Einstein’s general theory of relativity.

“[We] conjoin theories we accept. But positivist surrogates for truth, reference, and acceptance cannot underwrite this practice.”

“To accept a theory is to believe it is empirically adequate, but acceptance has further non-epistemic/pragmatic features. Empirical adequacy is logically weaker than truth: T’s truth entails its empirical adequacy but not conversely. But it [what’s ‘it’; truth or adequacy?] is still quite strong: an empirically adequate theory must correctly represent all the phenomena, both observed and unobserved. Epistemic acceptance is belief; beliefs are either true or false. Pragmatic acceptance involves non-epistemic commitments to use the theory in certain ways (basing research, experiments, and explanations on it, for example); commitments are neither true nor false; they are either vindicated or not. [Instrumental] acceptance suffices to account for scientific practice.”

Acceptance when there is no objectivity begs woe. The most egregious reasoning in the above collection of quotes may be the assertion that an “empirically adequate theory” can represent the unobserved by design. Second, instrumental acceptance seems erroneous, because better instruments and ways of using them are often invented.

Summary


Starting from the premise that I would like to encourage fellow citizens to accept the-objective-truth as the measure of truth and route to literal truth, I sought to inform myself about other uses of “acceptance” by reviewing philosophical articles. I found no survey article, but there are perhaps thousands of philosophical articles that use the word “acceptance.”


Here is a tabulation of dominant interpretations from the articles I read, by key words from their titles or my expression of the subject:


1.       Rule-consequences                        cultural constructs


2.       Constructive empiricism               belief: a dangerous practice


3.       Social institutions                             concurrent opinion or collectives


4.       Toleration                                           dominant opinion


5.       Awareness testimony                    closed minds divided by semantics


6.       Ethical belief                                      an oxymoron


7.       Natural semantics                            words that express humankind’s observables


8.       Logical conditionals                         rationalizing potential falsehoods


9.       Ancient skepticism                          reason overrules impression


10.   Egocentric awareness                    spiritual salvation a human hope


11.   The common good                          competition for dominant opinion


12.   Civilization                                           collective bemusement


13.   Research prevents emotions      discover the ineluctable evidence


14.   Antirealism                                         “we are entitled to” change the facts


The key observations from my limited study and comprehension are: Articles 1-4, 6, 8-12, and 14 or 11 of 14 or 79% attempt to justify a human construct so as to neglect the-objective-truth. Articles 5 and 7 address the importance of communicating, collaborating, and connecting in order to establish commonly defined words; for example, “whatever-God-is” is more expressive than “God.” Article 13 stresses that scientific research rejects the emotionalism of metaphysics. Support for research for discovery of ineluctable evidence is evident from negative interpretations or modern progress respecting some of the articles. For example, Article 9 can be expanded to make the point that justice reason overrules impression, ineluctable evidence overrules reason.


I would like to read a philosopher’s essay on “awareness.”


Copyright©2019 by Phillip R. Beaver. All rights reserved. Permission is hereby granted for the publication of all or portions of this paper as long as this complete copyright notice is included. Note on 10/6/19.




[1] “The-objective-truth” is my phrase to invite the reader to consider discovered, ineluctable evidence as having the potential to represent actual reality, lessened only by the human frailties of scientific research. When a researcher trusts-in and commits to the discovery of the-objective-truth, he or she remains constrained by the instruments that are available and other factors. He or she remains humble to the literal truth.
[5] “Actual reality” means factual existence or literal truth.
[6] This is my interpretation of a priori knowledge, a proprietary term.

No comments:

Post a Comment

I want your opinion and intend to respond.